|
Durable URL
The durable URL for this page/text is:
Copy and paste the link into your documents and email.
Criticism & Reference: Full Text
Save to My Archive |
Table of Contents |
Print View |
Durable URL for this text |
Download citation |
Email Full Text
Crane, Mary Thomas; Richardson, Alan.: Literary studies and cognitive science: toward a new interdisciplinarity.
Mosaic: a journal for the interdisciplinary study of literature (Univ. of Manitoba, Winnipeg) (32:2)
[Jun 1999]
,
p.123-140.
View Full Record

|
Mary Thomas Crane, Alan Richardson. Mosaic : a Journal for the Interdisciplinary Study of Literature. Winnipeg: Jun 1999.Vol. 32, Iss. 2; pg. 123, 18 pgs | Classification Codes | 9172 | Author(s): | Mary Thomas Crane, Alan Richardson | Document types: | Feature | Publication title: | Mosaic : a Journal for the Interdisciplinary Study of Literature. Winnipeg: Jun 1999. Vol. 32, Iss. 2; pg. 123, 18 pgs | Source type: | Periodical | ISSN/ISBN: | 00271276 | Text Word Count | 6857 | Abstract (Document Summary) | The cognitive sciences offer new paradigms for rethinking the relations among culture, linguistic activity, and agency. This essay provides an overview of the "cognitive revolution" and recent work on the brain, and then discusses the dominant strains within cognitive linguistics, arguing for wider applicability to literary theory and criticism. |
 Full Text (6857 words) |
Copyright MOSAIC Jun 1999
[Headnote] |
The cognitive sciences offer new paradigms
for rethinking the relations among culture, linguistic activity,
and agency. This essay provides an overview of the "cognitive
revolution" and recent work on the brain, and then discusses
the dominant strains within cognitive linguistics, arguing
for wider applicability to literary theory and criticism.
|
- Literary scholars have increasingly taken up interdisciplinary
frameworks, methodologies, and pursuits in recent years, despite
the difficulties of "being interdisciplinary" cogently outlined
by Stanley Fish. Such broad-based critical schools or tendencies
as the new historicism, gender studies, and cultural criticism
by definition stake out their ground between or across disciplines,
and some literature departments have remade themselves as
"cultural studies" programs, suggesting that interdisciplinarity
is becoming not simply a legitimate option for literary scholars
but may be gaining the force of an imperative-one all the
harder to resist as university presses attempt to maximize
sales with academic titles that can be marketed across disciplinary
lines.
- It might seem initially surprising, then, that those challenging
disciplinary boundaries in literary and cultural studies have
shown so little interest in cognitive science, the major interdisciplinary
initiative marking the convergence of linguistics, computer
science, psychology, neuroscience, philosophy of mind, and
anthropology. Our widespread lack of engagement with what
has been called the "cognitive revolution" is all the more
striking given its obvious bearing on theoretical discussions
of language, subjectivity, and consciousness, not to mention
its status as one of the most exciting and potentially far-reaching
intellectual developments of the late 20th century.
- We hope to provoke such engagement-both critical and collaborative-in
the essay that follows. We begin by sketching out some key
developments in the constitution of cognitive science as a
major interdisciplinary venture, emphasizing the transition
from pioneering attempts to describe cognition in terms of
the logical processing of coded symbols to more recent efforts
to ground cognitive activity in embodied experience. We then
look at a series of related issues in cognitive science of
special interest to scholars of literature and culture, including
categorization theory, nonarbitrary aspects of language, metaphoricity,
agency, and the material character of thought. Finally, we
survey a number of attempts to date, on the part of cognitive
researchers and theorists as well as literary scholars and
critics, to forge links between literary studies and cognitive
science.
- The first phase of the cognitive revolution, based initially
in linguistics and computer science, successfully dislodged
behaviorism as the dominant paradigm within the social sciences.
Behaviorism held that only directly observable behaviors could
provide a valid basis for scientific study, and that any speculation
about the cognitive processes behind those behaviors was insupportable
and therefore to be avoided. Reaching beyond the social sciences,
the influence of behaviorism was also apparent in the New
Critical "intentionalist fallacy"-with its injunction to study
only the text as a mode of complex behavior, leaving aside
any concern about the author's thoughts or intentions-and
in the "affective fallacy" which similarly bracketed off the
mental processes of the reader. Another behaviorist axiom,
that human behavior is determined by environmental or cultural
forces without reference to specific mental functions or constraints,
still inheres within several current approaches to literary
and cultural studies, such as Marxist and some new historicist
criticism.
- In fields such as linguistics and psychology, however, behaviorism
has for some time been largely discarded in favor of research
into the cognitive processes of the brain. Noam Chomsky was
the first outspoken critic of behaviorism, arguing in the
1950s that the human mind carried a linguistic capacity that
was both innate and universal. Chomsky's work focused mainly
on syntax, morphology, and phonology, and generally aimed
at an almost mathematical precision in the analysis of natural
language, leading his critics to charge him with having evaded
semantics, and for failing to account for meaning. Yet although
Chomsky's theories have remained controversial and have frequently
changed over the years, the tenets of innate and universal
human linguistic ability have found wide acceptance.
- At the same time that Chomsky's work was helping to shift
the attention of linguists toward the brain and toward the
identification of distinct and highly constrained patterns
produced by it, computer scientists were beginning to think
about the ways in which digital computers might resemble the
human brain, be made to simulate its workings, and, ultimately,
become "intelligent." Alan Turing, who pioneered the "strong
AI" position, argued that a digital computer functioned in
ways that were essentially similar to the human brain, and
that a computer would therefore eventually come to manifest
an artificial intelligence indistinguishable from human intelligence.
If a computer were able to hold a conversation with a person,
and that person were unable to tell the computer's responses
from those of a living person, the computer would pass the
"Turing test" and could legitimately be called intelligent.
- By the late 1950s, computer scientists were actively attempting
to build machines that could "think" rationally in ways similar
to human cognitive processes. For example, Allen Newell and
Herbert Simon constructed Logic Theorist, a program that could
prove theorems in logic, while others invented programs that
could play chess, solve algebra problems, or manipulate shapes
in an artificial universe. Such programs achieved limited
success, but proved ultimately inadequate in ways reminiscent
of Chomsky's early syntactic theories-they could manipulate
symbols that were defined within a logical and finite system,
but could not account for the messy complexities of the real
world. As philosopher Hubert Dreyfus puts it, "the research
program based on the assumption that human beings produce
intelligence using facts and rules has reached a dead end,
and there is no reason to think it could ever succeed" (ix).
Even current AI researchers such as Terry Winograd and Fernando
Flores believe that "in spite of a wide variety of ingenious
techniques for making analysis and recognition more flexible,
the scope of comprehension [of computers with reference to
natural languages] remains severely limited" (11). Earlier,
philosopher John Searle hit on this weakness in his famous
"Chinese room" essay, which argues that machines can never
truly understand the symbols that they manipulate with such
speed and precision. As he saw it, whereas human beings are
able to relate whatever symbols their brains manipulate with
meaningful events in the "real world" that their bodies inhabit
and constantly negotiate, computers will never be able to
do so. Indeed, attempts to have computers perform more complex
functions have tended to be least successful wherever "meaning"
or knowledge of the world have been most critical.
- Early cognitive theory thus eventually ran up against the
limitations of its overly logical model of the mind and its
inability to account for the complex ways in which human beings
interact with the lived world. Some AI researchers, accordingly,
began to develop computers based more closely on what was
being learned about the architecture of the brain, employing
more complex "neural nets" rather than simpler and more logical
serial processing. Artificial neural networks, however, have
as yet nothing like the massive and intricate connectedness
of actual neurons, and in general, as helpful as computer
models have proved in testing theories about basic cognitive
functions, their ultimate usefulness has been essentially
paradoxical: their attempts to prove that the human mind functions
logically in ways that resemble a digital computer have failed,
demonstrating, instead, that human cognitive functioning makes
extensive use of "heuristics, strategies, biases, images,
and other vague and approximate approaches" (Gardner 385).
Concurrently, research in psychology, anthropology, and neuroscience
has, in different ways, helped shape a view of the mind which
addresses the shortfalls of Chomskian linguistics and strong
AI theory.
- Cognitive scientists now tend to posit a mind that, because
of its biological and embodied features, is inextricably implicated
with thought processes that seem emotional, metaphorical,
and in many ways "illogical" in comparison to the serial logic
and separation of cognition and emotion that characterized
early cognitive theory. What first suggested alternatives
to a strictly logical view of cognition was research-linking
linguistics, psychology, and anthropology-that explored the
cross-cultural uses of basic color terms. For example, working
with the Dani in New Guinea, who possess only two color terms
roughly equivalent to "light" and "dark," Eleanor Rosch found
to her surprise that despite this limited verbal range, the
Dani seemed to perceive colors in ways highly similar to speakers
of languages with much more extensive color vocabularies.
Rosch's work in the 1970s lent fuel to the cognitive attack
on behaviorism, demonstrating that the perception of color
represents another area of cognition where innate capabilities
help shape linguistic behavior.
- Rosch (and later investigators) further suggested that the
division of colors into categories does not operate in accordance
with classical theories of categorization. As John Taylor
explains, classical logic posits categories that are clearly
bound, equal in status, and composed of necessary and sufficient
features that are discriminated along binary lines (2324).
In terms of color, this would mean that something categorized
as "red" would necessarily share all of the same features
(in this case, a particular range of wave-lengths of light)
with all other reds; a given color would either be "red" or
"not-red;' the difference between "red" and "notred" would
be clearly defined, and all reds would be equally red. Rosch
found instead that the human cognitive system categorizes
not by a list of features, but on the basis of a prototypical
member (the reddest red). While the membership of that red
in the category would be clear, other instances of red would
be less clearly "red." This kind of "radial" category, anticipated
by Wittgenstein's theory of "family resemblance;' has fuzzy
boundaries, with some instances of reddish-blue or bluish-red
that cannot definitively be placed in either the red or blue
camp. Prototype effects were also found to structure categories
like "birds," "vegetables," and "furniture."
- George Lakoff (a linguist) and Mark Johnson (a philosopher)
have extended these insights to posit cognitive functions
that emerge from the human experience of living in a body
and that are extended metaphorically (in radial categories)
to classify and characterize even the most abstract concepts.
One of these basic spatial schemas is "containment," which
structures not only thinking about our location in space but
also the way we express concepts in language-e.g. the widespread
metaphor that words "contain" ideas. Thought and its representation
in language, then, are shaped not solely or even primarily
by cultural forces but also by the innate and universal physical
parameters of our bodies and brains, as we attempt to make
sense of and successfully negotiate what surrounds us, in
nature and culture. Neuroscientists working both at the level
of brain cells (neurons) and with larger brain structures
and functional neuronal groupings (like the hippocampus, the
amygdala, and the visual cortex) have arrived at a similar
view of categorization and of the basic interrelatedness of
mind, brain, body, and environment. Gerald Edelman, for example,
explicitly presents his theory of neuronal group selection
as a "biological underpinning" for Lakoff and Johnson's work
on linguistic and conceptual categories (246-52). In turn,
in arguing for a fundamentally embodied, anti-dualistic account
of the mind-brain on the basis of neurological observation
and experimental study, Antonio Damasio cites Rosch, Lakoff,
Johnson, and Edelman as all having arrived at the central
notion of a "body-minded brain" along converging routes (223-44).
- The implications of these newer cognitive-neuroscientific
theories of the mind for our currently dominant literary theoretical
paradigms are potentially as revolutionary as was Chomsky's
challenge to behaviorism. Consider, for example, how prototype
theory crucially departs from Saussurean linguistics, the
taking-off point for much post-modern theory. Saussure put
forward two basic propositions about meaning: 1 ) that linguistic
signs are arbitrary with respect both to the connection between
phonetic form and meaning, and that between meaning and the
world; and 2) that language is a closed system within which
concepts are constituted out of their difference from other
terms in the system, without reference to any extra-systemic
reality. Rosch's work, however, suggests that linguistic meaning
(as opposed to a given signifier/signified pairing) is not
arbitrary, but is instead "motivated" by experiences of perception
and embodiment.
- According to Saussure, the signifier RED is arbitrarily
linked with the experience of perceiving the color "red,"
which is itself based on an arbitrary (and culturally determined)
division of the spectrum. According to cognitive linguistic
theory, the link between the word RED and the color is still,
of course, arbitrary, but the experience of redness is not;
it is, instead, based on the fact that a specific range of
wavelengths of light excite a particular set of cells in the
human retina in a certain way. All human beings thus experience
the prototypical color red in essentially the same way, and
whatever their name for it, the concept of "redness" is motivated
by physical experience. Furthermore, according to Saussure,
RED is defined as red because it is not blue or green; the
spectrum is thus carved up arbitrarily in pieces which are
defined by their differences from all other relevant terms
in the linguistic system. According to cognitive theory, however,
a red is red because it resembles the prototypical red. Nor
can red be definitively separated from blue, although there
will be a prototypical blue from which it can easily be discerned.
Thus, cognitive theory posits concepts that are not simply
determined by the symbolic order in which they exist; instead,
meanings are formed by an interaction of the physical world,
culture, and human cognitive systems.
- Other prevailing paradigms challenged by cognitive semiotics
can be found within post-structuralist theory, which at first
glance would seem to have close affinities. The Derridean
critique of Western rationalism, for example, seems to parallel
the cognitivist claim that rational thought does not comprise
the natural functioning of the human cognitive system, just
as Derrida's deconstruction of binaries can be seen as compatible
with the cognitive insight that categorization is not structured
by binary opposition, but by a gradient of resemblance to
a prototype. When Derrida attributes to Western culture the
view that "metaphoricity is the logic of contamination and
the contamination of logic" (Dissemination 149), his argument
overlaps with the cognitive linguist's sense that the metaphoric
basis of human cognition places it at odds with most systems
of formal logic. Cognitive linguistics, however, also challenges
or modifies some post-structuralist concepts. Derrida, for
instance, assumes Saussurean postulates of arbitrariness and
definition by difference, even though he questions Saussure's
phonocentric bias (Of Grammatology 2773). However, if meaning
is not arbitrary but motivated, then slippage of meaning is
at least partially bounded or anchored by its physical motivations.
In addition, when Derrida argues that "there is nothing outside
the text" he can be seen as postulating what amounts to a
particularly sophisticated version of the behaviorist refusal
to consider the systems and processes that produce behavior,
whereas it is precisely these systems and processes that cognitive
linguistics wants to investigate.
- Post-structuralism and cognitive science stand to gain from
critical juxtaposition since each has blind spots which the
other may usefully illuminate. F. Elizabeth Hart has recently
argued that cognitive linguistics can provide a more thoroughly
materialist approach to language, meaning, and culture than
can a Derridean post-structuralism still haunted by "residual
formalism" ("Matter, System" 5). Hart suggests that this formalism
has been carried over into the work of cultural materialist
and new historicist criticism and prevents such criticism
from acknowledging the complex and reciprocal relationship
of culture and the embodied mind in forming the human subject.
The critical paradigm which is most directly challenged by
cognitive linguistics is thus that informed by Foucauldian
assumptions about human behavior, for while cognitive science
does give a large role to the shaping power of culture, it
also stresses the role of innate mental dispositions and innately
constrained cognitive procedures that hold across cultures
and historical eras.
- The Dani encountered by Rosch, for example, with no word
for "red," will nevertheless point to the same prototypical
red as the best example of the color, and will identify roughly
the same range of shades as belonging to that category. Linguist-anthropologists
Brent Berlin and Paul Kay found that cultures develop words
for colors according to a universal pattern: if a culture
has two terms, they will designate focal black and white,
a third term will always be red, and a fourth term will be
yellow or green, followed by blue, then brown, then gray,
orange, pink and purple in no particular order. This suggests
that while colors may exist in nature as an undifferentiated
spectrum of light, the human perceptual system, even across
cultures, will divide them in predictable ways. The number
of color terms a given culture possesses is, of course, determined
by cultural factors, and in general, the more complex the
concept or topic, the more important are culturally determined
elements in shaping its contours. Still, while research on
categorization of concepts more complex than color suggests
that there are striking cultural differences in the nature
of prototypical examples for each category, it also demonstrates
that these categories are structured in similar ways across
cultures. Cognitive science, in short, does not rule out the
role of cultural construction but promises more flexible and
productive methods for studying the multiple and complex intersections
of culture and human cognition as they influence and shape
each other.
- Competing accounts of human and authorial agency offered
by different cognitive scientists at times support, and at
times counter post-structuralist assumptions. Some computer
scientists especially have theorized a human subjectivity
that is as fragmented as that posited by Lacan (or by the
contemporary neo-Lacanian Slovoj Zizek), most notably Marvin
Minsky's conception of the mind as a "society" of multiple
agents working in parallel fashion without centralized control.
Similarly, the philosopher Daniel Dennett has devoted himself
to debunking the common illusion of a homunculus or "little
man" in the brain who both watches and directs conscious activity
in a theater of the mind, proposing instead a model of contending
agents or "demons" who produce a continually disrupted "stream
of consciousness" from "multiple drafts"-a model that Dennett
himself has compared to David Lodge's "faithful paraphrase"
of deconstructionist theory in his academic satire Nice Work
(Spolsky 39).
- Other computer scientists and cognitive philosophers, however,
leave room for the "emergence" of agency through the massive
integration of neural activity. Neuroscientists seem especially
willing to posit an integrated cognitive system, although
they also clearly acknowledge a brain that has many different
parts with functions that are to some extent separately localized.
Edelman allows for a "personal individuality" that emerges
from developmental and social interactions (167), while maintaining
a more than Freudian insistence on the unavailability of much
mental activity to conscious introspection and an acknowledgment
of the presence of the "other" in our linguistically-based
consciousness (146). Damasio, while denying that "all the
contents of our minds are inspected by a single central knower
and owner," nevertheless argues that "our experiences tend
to have a consistent perspective" which is "rooted in a relatively
stable, endlessly repeated biological state" (238). Damasio
further revives something like a notion of "will" when he
argues that rational decision-making functions in the brain
are powerfully influenced by emotion. Cognitive scientists
thus acknowledge a partitioned subject but also find suggestive
ways to discuss our persistent belief that we possess integrated
selves.
- Cognitive theory also provides an incentive to rethink the
Marxist views on the materiality of language and its role
in material culture. Such criticism has to a great extent
based its theory of language in Saussure and has moreover
adopted a behaviorist refusal to consider cognitive processes.
Marxist linguists like David Silverman and Brian Torode argue
that "linguistic communication consists in the transmission
of immaterial ideas or concepts from one person (speaker or
writer) to another (reader or listener) by means of material
signs," and since those immaterial ideas are located (by Saussure)
in the brain and "the brain is unavailable to the researcher,"
then "its content, conceptual or otherwise, remains mysterious,
and can only be the subject of speculation or arbitrary assumption"
(3). It is no longer necessary or advantageous, however, to
"black box" the brain in this fashion. The cognitive neurosciences
have made the brain increasingly available to researchers
and almost all cognitive theorists believe that the mind is
essentially material since, as Kosslyn and Koenig put it,
"the mind is what the brain does" (4). Damasio, Edelman, Lakoff
and others have emphasized the ways in which human cognition
is deeply influenced by its materiality and embodiment. Materialist
criticism may thus need to begin to consider the implications
of the brain as the material site where culture and biology
meet and shape each other. Althusser, indeed, leaves room
for such consideration when he argues that it is important
to distinguish desire from "the biological realities that
support it (exactly as biological existence supports historical
existence) but neither constitute, nor determine it," even
if that supporting role remains unexamined in his work (213n6).
- Finally, materialist studies of literature will profit from
acknowledging the brain as the material site where language,
culture, and the body meet and form each other. Foucault's
influential redirection of questions about the author's cognitive
processes to questions about the place of authorship in material
culture should be supplemented by a more thorough materialism
that recognizes a stage of existence and circulation of discourse
within the author's material body. This recognition would
take the form of scrutiny of texts not only for traces of
ideological formations or cultural systems, but for traces
of cognitive process as well. Literary studies will also need
to pay new attention to various writers' attempts, through
history, to imagine, understand, and represent their own cognitive
processes. Critics will have cause to reopen topics that will
help to redraw the boundaries between body and culture: the
effects of psychoactive drugs, for instance, or the physical
manifestations of emotion, or the mental effects of physical
experiences such as pain.
- While much remains to be done, for over a decade now a handful
of scholars working in literature departments, and a few others
in computer science and cognitive psychology, have in fact
been moving toward the convergence of cognitive science and
literary studies largely without reference to one another's
work. We might begin with Norman Holland's The Brain of Robert
Frost (1988), which he claims as the "first book to bring
to bear on literary criticism and theory the revolutionary
discoveries of cognitive science and recent research into
the brain" (vi), although Frederick Turner had included several
chapters on literature and the brain a few years earlier in
Natural Classicism (1985) and Revuen Tsur had been working
in the field of "cognitive poetics" since the 1970s. Holland,
wellknown for his psychoanalytical approach to reader-response
theory, makes a strong case for replacing the social constructionist
paradigm of mind relied on in most literary theory with the
"more powerful psychology" emerging from cognitive neuroscience
(6, 13). Tracing the social constructionist paradigm back
to the "stimulus-response" model of early 20th-century behaviorism,
Holland is especially persuasive in proposing a more active
and fine-grained sense of the reader's work of cognitive processing
in reader-response studies, and he rightly emphasizes the
critical role of"experience"-and thus of social context and
genetic development, history and biography-in neuroscientific
accounts of the mind (7-8).
- Holland's desire to retain central elements of psychoanalytic
theory along with new insights from cognitive science, however,
produces a book which does not fully realize the potential
of a brain-based psychological literary criticism; his psychological
portrait of Frost, for example, reads very much like conventional
Freudian psychobiography (16-42). Tsur's weighty and wide-ranging
Toward a Theory of Cognitive Poetics (1992), which synthesizes
twenty-five years of research, is characterized by an even
greater sense of eclecticism; in attempting to develop new
approaches to versification, figural language, emotive effects,
and critical response he draws upon early Gestalt psychology,
Russian and Prague school formalism, psycholinguistics, the
New Criticism, and structuralism as well as cognitive science.
If the "cognitive" elements of his theory often fail to emerge
cleanly, Tsur offers a wealth of leads and insights and some
of his findings seem especially useful-such as his cross-linguistic
theory of poetic caesurae (134-39), which overlaps suggestively
with Frederick Turner's "universal" theory of the poetic line
(61-108).
- Two books more pervasively conversant with cognitive linguistics
and categorization theory, Mark Turner's Reading Minds (1991)
and Ellen Spolsky's Gaps in Nature (1993), provide readable,
engaging, and sophisticated examples of how literary scholars
can both profit from and contribute to work in the cognitive
sciences. Turner, who has collaborated with Lakoff, delineates
a "cognitive rhetoric" which ties literary experience to our
everyday (but largely unnoticed or unconscious) activities
of conceptualization, categorization, and, especially, invention
and interpretation of metaphors and other rhetorical figures.
Turner's rich sense of connectedness among the language-producing
human brain, the body that includes it, and the "physical
environment that it must make intelligible if it is to survive"
( 17), as well as his informed speculation on the likely neural
substrates of such adaptive, creative linguistic and literary
activity, give his work a strong sense of conviction. Some
literary scholars, however, have raised objections to his
call for a "new common ground" and large-scale reconstitution
of the "profession of English" on the basis of cognitive linguistics,
a field that he himself characterizes as still speculative
and "embryonic"(vii-viii, 20).
- Spolsky is less interested in explicating the extraordinary
productivity of ordinary linguistic competence than in theorizing
how the mind's inherent "cognitive instability"-arising from
the gaps and incommensurabilities among various brain functions
and the fundamental neuronal plasticity that keep categories
fuzzy and concepts fluid-makes possible the literary innovation
we find in "culture's most powerfully imaginative texts" as
well as in our own attempts to rewrite literary history (2,
4, 7). For Spolsky, supplementing cultural materialism with
a "materialist, biologically based" model of the mind-brain
helps account for innovation within what might otherwise seem
a linguistic and cultural prison-house: resistance to "reigning
cultural patterns" stems from the brain's stubborn materiality,
the friction between functional modules or neuronal groups
dedicated to divergent sensory and motor domains (206). Her
illustrations of such resistance from feminist criticism and
ecriture feminine are of particular interest given how little
attention to gender has been paid by cognitive approaches
to date, although her distinctions between "associative" thinking,
"presocialized feelings," and feminist modes of discourse
on the one hand, and traditional (male) "logical/deductive"
modes on the other, seem open to the critiques directed at
other forms of "difference" feminism (202-04).
- Two researchers in computer science, Jerry Hobbs (in Literature
and Cognition) and Herbert Simon (in the target essay for
Bridging the Gap, a special issue of the Stanford Humanities
Review) bring their own disciplinary perspective to bear on
issues of literary theory and criticism. Having spent years
prodding machines to decode natural utterances like "we're
having our new colleague for dinner Thursday" without invoking
the "Urban Cannibal" script, they are in a good position to
charge literary theorists with portraying human text processing
as more difficult and ambiguous than need be. Their position
of relative detachment can produce unexpected and refreshing
insights on such matters as intention (how is the text produced
by a pocket calculator "intentional"?) and context (what rules
do we tacitly follow in delimiting the potentially limitless
set of contexts for a given text?). Both Hobbs and Simon,
however, fail adequately to account for the emotive aspects
of literary production and reception and, as Mark Turner points
out in his cogent response to Simon, they ignore to their
cost that "a human brain resides in a human body in a human
environment" ("Cognitive Science" 111). A few of the other
responses in Bridging the Gap assail Simon and cognitive science
in general with little or no sense of the diversity of cognitive
approaches or the debates among various cognitive theorists
and neuroscientists. Such wholesale resistance underscores
that considering a given cognitive theorist's work without
some knowledge of the larger cognitive enterprise can all
too readily lead to incomprehension. Scholars who would begin
the important work of gauging the usefulness of neural and
cognitive models for literary studies would do well to explore
various tendencies before choosing any one for specific critique,
or, for that matter, endorsement.
- Some narratologists have begun turning to AI and other fields
within cognitive science in an effort to rejuvenate their
field. For example, Gary Saul Morson, in his foreword to a
recent reissue of Roger Schank's Tell Me a Story, credits
Schank (an important AI pioneer) with having "reinvented"
the discipline of narratology (ix). Morson finds particularly
refreshing Schank's emphasis on the "amazing web of ordinary
and surprisingly complex responses that comprise daily life"-an
emphasis that aligns Schank's work on narrative and intelligence
with Mark Turner's recent work on parable and "narrative imagining"
(Literary Mind 4-5), both viewing story-telling as a pervasive
and highly adaptive aspect of mental life, tying our most
quotidian acts of problem solving to literary creativity.
Morson also identifies, quite intriguingly, an area of common
ground between Schank's work on the pervasiveness of story
in social discourse and the dialogic theory of discourse developed
by the Bakhtin group (xix-xx, xxxi). Similarly, Marie-Laure
Ryan finds in AI (as well as in "possible worlds" theory)
an urgently needed "new source of ideas" for narratology:
she fundamentally recasts, for example, conventional narratological
notions of framing or embedding by appealing instead to the
model of "stacking" employed in AI, showing how reconceptualizing
narrative as a "computer language" can account for the complex
metafictional effects notoriously resistant to traditional
narratology (3, 175).
- Another promising site for new interdisciplinary work has
been mapped out by cognitive psychologists, who share with
computer scientists a vocabulary of "scripts" and "story grammars,"
"scenarios" and "text processing," and who have begun to apply
their considerable knowledge of language comprehension to
specifically literary topics. Richard Gerrig and Raymond Gibbs
have both produced books that emphasize the continuities between
literary experience and everyday linguistic production and
comprehension. Gerrig, in Experiencing Narrative Worlds, and
Gibbs, in The Poetics of Mind, draw on hundreds of experimental
studies which decompose and clarify the cognitive work performed
by readers in discriminating, interpreting, remembering, and
paraphrasing literary and nonliterary texts alike. In the
spirit of Lakoff, Johnson, and Turner, both Gerrig and (especially)
Gibbs argue that conventionally "literary" topics like narrative
and figurative language are central rather than peripheral
to understanding the basic workings of human cognition, revealing
what Gibbs calls the "poetic structure of mind" (2). While
both psychologists draw on literary theory and criticism in
filling out their "poetic" accounts of mental life, however,
neither has much to say about possible material substrates
or additional evidence from neuroscience, although as early
as 1978 Howard Gardner and Ellen Winner had noted the value
of such evidence, for literary scholars and philosophers as
well as for cognitive psychologists ("Development").
- David Rubin, in contrast, does consider neuroscientific
evidence in Memory in Oral Traditions, his groundbreaking
and inclusive study of what the ability to memorize various
forms of oral poetry reveals about mental functioning and
how, in turn, the nature of human memory shapes elements of
such poetic forms on many levels, from alliterative word pairings
to large-scale narrative structures. Summing up and refining
a whole tradition of empirical work on memory and generously
providing more information than is strictly necessary about
the principles and methods of cognitive psychology as a kind
of ongoing tutorial for the student of literature, Rubin has
provided one of the most important and useful examples to
date of how cognitive science can help illuminate traditionally
literary concerns.
- Other literary scholars adapting empirical methods from
the cognitive neurosciences to reconsider or reopen literary
questions include David Miall and several contributors to
a recently published volume on Empirical Approaches to Literature
and Aesthetics (Kreuz & MacNealy). In an empirical study
of "literariness," Miall argues for regrounding readerresponse
criticism on the "reasonably clear neuropsychological evidence"
emerging from studies by Damasio and others on the interrelation
of cognitive and affective functions: he outlines a research
program for elucidating the effects of literary foregrounding
and other anticipatory elements of the reading process in
terms of what is being learned about affective anticipation
and links between the prefronal cortex and the limbic system
(294-95). Miall cites work-in-progress by Johan Hoorn (later
published in Empirical Approaches) on "psychophysiology and
literary processing" that has established, through measuring
event-related potentials with EEG (electroencephalogram) recordings,
the salience of the "deviation" effects in poetic language
theorized by Slavic formalist critics. Tom Barney, another
contributor to the volume Empirical Approaches, attempts to
bring work on stylistics (particularly metrics) into line
with the psycholinguistic research into phonetics, and W.
John Harker argues that cognitive research into attentional
behavior in text processing can help account for felt differences
in reading literary and nonliterary works.
- Yet however intriguing the preliminary results, and however
timely the acknowledgment that findings from scientific research
can help delimit and redirect literary investigations, empirical
studies should by no means be thought of as the only, or even
the principal, way for students of literature to profit from
work on the brain and cognition. Elaine Scarry, in one of
the most impressive essays in literary criticism yet to engage
with cognitive neuroscience, draws on work by Stephen Kosslyn
and others on mental imagery to reopen the old question of
the "vivacity" of the literary imagination: why do images
evoked by the reading of certain literary texts seem so vivid,
given the flatness of mental images in general? Her methodology
relies almost entirely on the sort of rich introspection and
literary tact that scholars of literature, with years of attentive
reading and a good deal of insightful published analysis to
build on, are uniquely trained to bring to textual interpretation,
qualities that in fact are highly valued by Hobbs and other
cognitive scientists. Scarry herself, however, is now working
with Kosslyn to design empirical tests, using magnetic resonance
imaging (MRI) scanning, of her hypotheses concerning literary
devices and mental imagery (Magner), suggesting that the intuitions
of trained readers can provide models for confirmatory research
in controlled settings.
- The dizzying progress of cognitive and neuroscientific research
over the past twenty years has produced a large number of
models and findings of pressing relevance to such literary
topics as prosody, narrative poetics, reader response, figural
language, genre theory, and imagery. In addition, theorists
can be expected to feel the pressure to begin rethinking received
notions like the arbitrariness of the linguistic-conceptual
field, the sociocultural constructedness of the self, and
the bracketing-off of the neural substrates of mental activity.
Indeed, literary scholars like F. Elizabeth Hart have already
begun looking to the "cognitive linguistics" of the Lakoff
group, for example, for its disclosure of a "middle space
in the dichotomy between determinacy and indeterminacy" bedevilling
current literary theory and for its capacity to "demysify
figurative language" and describe its effects in compelling
ways unavailable both to structuralist and deconstructionist
positions ("Cognitive Linguistics" 22). There is also an opening
for what might be called a "neural historicism," which would
explore how the peculiar structure and workings of the human
brain may enable cultural innovation over time and offer revisionary
accounts of the representation of mind and mental processes
in literary-cultural history along new lines suggested by
the frameworks and models emerging from the cognitive neurosciences.
Conversely, recent work in cognitive rhetoric and the "poetics
of mind" presents an invitation to literary scholars and theorists
to bring their particular expertise to bear, as collaborators,
critics, or both, on the further development of cognitive
science. It is worth recalling that one of the more fruitful
distinctions in 20th-century literary studies, that between
metaphor and metonymy as opposite poles of both linguistic
and literary activity, was formulated by the linguist and
poetician Roman Jakobson as a contribution toward the development
of early neuropsychology. Those willing to cross disciplinary
lines in the age of cognitive science stand to contribute
similarly productive models and to elicit a whole range of
new meanings in the texts, practices, and historical and cultural
configurations that we study.*
[Footnote] |
*We wish to thank Deborah Blacker, Margaret
Thomas, Mark Turner, and Ellen Winner for their comments
and suggestions on various drafts of this essay. |
[Reference] |
Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy
and Other Essays. Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly
Review, 1971. |
Barney, Tom. "Phonetics and the Empirical
Study of Poetry." Kreuz and MacNealy 309-28. |
Berlin, Brent, and Paul Kay. Basic Color
Terms: Their Universality and Evolution. Berkeley: U of
California P, 1969. |
Dennett, D. C. Content and Consciousness.
London: Routledge, 1969. |
Derrida, Jacques. Dissemination. Trans.
Barbara Johnson. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1981. |
-.Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri Chakravortry
Spivak. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1976. |
[Reference] |
Damasio, Antonio. Descartes' Error:
Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Avon, 1994.
|
[Reference] |
Dreyfus, Hubert. What Computers Still
Can't Do. Cambridge: MIT P, 1992. |
Edelman, Gerald. Bright Air, Brilliant
Fire: On the Matter of Mind. New York: Basic, 1993. |
Fish, Stanley. "Being Interdisciplinary
Is So Very Hard to Do." Profession 89. New York: MLA, 1989.
15-22. |
Gardner, Howard. The Mind's New Science:
A History of the Cognitive Revolution. New York: Basic,
1985. |
[Reference] |
Gardner, Howard, and Ellen Winner. "The
Development of Metaphoric Competence: Implications for Humanistic
Disciplines." Critical Inquiry 5 (1978):123-41. |
Gerrig, Richard J. Experiencing Narrative
Worlds: On the Psychological Activities of Reading. New
Haven: Yale UP, 1993. |
Gibbs, Raymond W., Jr. The Poetics of
Mind: Figurative Thought, Language, and Understanding. Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1994. |
Harker, W. John. "Toward a Defensible
Psychology of Literary Interpretation." Kreuz and MacNealy
645-58. |
Hart, E Elizabeth. "Cognitive Linguistics:
The Experiential Dynamics of Metaphor." Mosaic 28.1 (1995):
1-23. |
-. "Matter, System, and Early Modern
Studies: Outlines for a Materialist Linguistics." Configurations
6 (1998): 311-43. |
Hildreth, Ellen C., and Shimon Ullman.
"The Computational Study of Vision." Posner 527-80. |
[Reference] |
Hobbs, Jerry. Literature and Cognition.
Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information,
1990. |
Holland, Norman N. The Brain of Robert
Frost. New York: Routledge, 1988. |
Hoorn, Johann. "Psychophysiology and
Literary Processing: ERP's to Semantic and Phonetic Deviations
in Reading Small Verses." Kreuz and MacNealy 339-58. |
Jakobson, Roman. "The Two Aspects of
Language and the Two Types of Aphasic Disturbance." On Language.
Ed. Linda R. Waugh and Monique Monville-Burston. Cambridge:
Harvard UP, 1990.115-33. |
[Reference] |
Kosslyn, Stephen, and Olivier Koenig.
Wet Mind: The New Cognitive Neuroscience. New York: Free
P, 1992. |
Kreuz, Roger J., and Mary Sue MacNealy,
eds. Empirical Approaches to Literature and Aesthetics.
Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1996. |
Lakoff, George. Women, Fire, and Dangerous
Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago:
U of Chicago P, 1987. |
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Metaphors
We Live By. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1980. |
Lakoff, George, and Mark Turner. More
than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago:
U of Chicago P, 1989. |
[Reference] |
Magner, Denise K. "A Program on the
Mind Changes Faculty Work at Harvard." Chronicle of Higher
Education 28 Feb. 1997: A12-14. |
Miall, David S. Anticipation and Feeling
in Literary Response: A Neuropsychological Perspective."
Poetics 23 (1995): 275-98. |
Minsky, Marvin. The Society of Mind.
New York: Simon,1985. |
Morson, Gary Saul. "Foreword." Tell
Me a Story: Narrative and Intelligence. By Roger C. Schank.
Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1995. ix-xl. |
Paivio, Allan. "The Mind's Eye in Arts
and Science."Poetics 12 (1983): 1-18. |
Pinker, Steven. The Language Instinct:
How the Mind Creates Language. New York: Harper, 1994. |
[Reference] |
Posner, Michael I., ed. Foundations
of Cognitive Science. 1989. Cambridge: MIT P, 1993. |
Rubin, David C. Memory in Oral Traditions:
The Cognitive Psychology of Epic, Ballads, and Counting-out
Rhymes. New York: Oxford UP, 1995. |
Ryan, Marie-Laure. Possible Worlds,
Artificial Intelligence, and Narrative Theory. Bloomington:
Indiana UP, 1991. |
Scarry, Elaine. "On Vivacity: The Difference
Between Daydreaming and Imagining-UnderAuthorial Instruction."
Representations 52 (1995): 1-26. |
Searle, John. "Minds, Brains, and Programs.'
The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1980): 417-57. |
[Reference] |
Silverman, David, and Brian Torode.
The Material Word: Some Theories of Language and its Limits.
Boston: Routledge, 1980. |
Simon, Herbert. "Literary Criticism:
A Cognitive Approach." Bridging the Gap: Where Cognitive
Science Meets Literary Criticism. Special Issue of Stanford
Humanities Review 4.1 (1994): 1-26. |
Spolsky, Ellen. Gaps in Nature: Literary
Interpretation and the Modular Mind. Albany: SUNY P, 1993.
|
[Reference] |
Taylor, John. Linguistic Categorization:
Prototypes in Linguistic Theory. 2nd. Ed. Oxford: Clarendon,
1995. |
Tsur, Reuven. Toward a Theory of Cognitive
Poetics. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1992. |
Turing, Alan. "Computing Machinery and
Intelligence." Computers and Thought. Ed. E. A. Feigenbaum
and J. Feldman. New York: McGraw Hill, 1963. |
[Reference] |
Turner, Frederick. Natural Classicism:
Essays on Literature and Science. New York: Paragon, 1985.
|
[Reference] |
Turner, Mark. "Cognitive Science and
Literary Theory." Bridging the Gap: Where Cognitive Science
Meets Literary Criticism. Special Issue of Stanford Humanities
Review 4.1 (1994): 110-12. |
-. The Literary Mind. New York: Oxford
UP, 1996. |
-. Reading Minds: The Study of English
in the Age of Cognitive Science. Princeton: Princeton UP,
1991. |
Wasow, Thomas. "Grammatical Theory."
Posner 161-205. |
Winograd, Terry, and Fernando Flores.
Understanding Computers and Cognition: A New Foundation
for Design. Reading, MA: Addison, 1986. |
[Author Affiliation] |
MARY THOMAS CRANE is Associate Professor
of English at Boston College and the author of Framing Authority:
Sayings, Self, and Society in Sixteenth-Century England.
She is currently working on cognitive approaches to Shakespeare's
plays. |
[Author Affiliation] |
ALAN RICHARDSON is Professor of English
at Boston College and the author of Literature, Education,
and Romanticism: Reading as Social Practice, 1780-1832.
He is completing a book about the interrelations between
British Romantic literature and early brain science with
the working title, "Neural Romanticism." |
|
 | Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction or distribution is prohibited without permission.
Return to top
|